Lemma 7.25.4. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a site. Let $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$. The functor $j_{U!}$ gives an equivalence of categories
Proof. Let us denote objects of $\mathcal{C}/U$ as pairs $(X, a)$ where $X$ is an object of $\mathcal{C}$ and $a : X \to U$ is a morphism of $\mathcal{C}$. Similarly, objects of $\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})/h_ U^\# $ are pairs $(\mathcal{F}, \varphi )$. The functor $\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}/U) \to \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})/h_ U^\# $ sends $\mathcal{G}$ to the pair $(j_{U!}\mathcal{G}, \gamma )$ where $\gamma $ is the composition of $j_{U!}\mathcal{G} \to j_{U!}*$ with the identification $j_{U!}* = h_ U^\# $.
Let us construct a functor from $\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})/h_ U^\# $ to $\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}/U)$. Suppose that $(\mathcal{F}, \varphi )$ is given. For an object $(X, a)$ of $\mathcal{C}/U$ we consider the set $\mathcal{F}_\varphi (X, a)$ of elements $s \in \mathcal{F}(X)$ which under $\varphi $ map to the image of $a \in \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(X, U) = h_ U(X)$ in $h_ U^\# (X)$. It is easy to see that $(X, a) \mapsto \mathcal{F}_\varphi (X, a)$ is a sheaf on $\mathcal{C}/U$. Clearly, the rule $(\mathcal{F}, \varphi ) \mapsto \mathcal{F}_\varphi $ defines a functor $\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})/h_ U^\# \to \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}/U)$.
Consider also the functor $\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})/h_ U \to \textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C}/U)$, $(\mathcal{F}, \varphi ) \mapsto \mathcal{F}_\varphi $ where $\mathcal{F}_\varphi (X, a)$ is defined as the set of elements of $\mathcal{F}(X)$ mapping to $a \in h_ U(X)$. We claim that the diagram
commutes, where the vertical arrows are given by sheafification. To see this1, it suffices to prove that the construction commutes with the functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}^+$ of Lemmas 7.10.3 and 7.10.4 and Theorem 7.10.10. Commutation with $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}^+$ follows from the fact that given $(X, a)$ the categories of coverings of $(X, a)$ in $\mathcal{C}/U$ and coverings of $X$ in $\mathcal{C}$ are canonically identified.
Next, let $\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C}/U) \to \textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})/h_ U$ send $\mathcal{G}$ to the pair $(j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{G}, \gamma )$ where $j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{G}$ the presheaf defined by the formula in Lemma 7.25.2 and $\gamma $ is the composition of $j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{G} \to j_{U!}*$ with the identification $j_{U!}^{PSh}* = h_ U$ (obvious from the formula). Then it is immediately clear that the diagram
commutes, where the vertical arrows are sheafification. Putting everything together it suffices to show there are functorial isomorphisms $(j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{G})_\gamma = \mathcal{G}$ for $\mathcal{G}$ in $\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C}/U)$ and $j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{F}_\varphi = \mathcal{F}$ for $(\mathcal{F}, \varphi )$ in $\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})/h_ U$. The value of the presheaf $(j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{G})_\gamma $ on $(X, a)$ is the fibre of the map
over $a$ which is $\mathcal{G}(X, a)$. This proves the first equality. The value of the presheaf $j_{U!}^{PSh}\mathcal{F}_\varphi $ is on $X$ is
because given a set map $S \to S'$ the set $S$ is the disjoint union of its fibres. $\square$
Post a comment
Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.
In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$
). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).
All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.
Comments (2)
Comment #6029 by Owen on
Comment #6176 by Johan on