Lemma 56.7.1. Let $X$ and $Y$ be Noetherian schemes. Let $F : \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X) \to \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$ be a functor. Then $F$ extends uniquely to a functor $\mathit{QCoh}(\mathcal{O}_ X) \to \mathit{QCoh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$ which commutes with filtered colimits. If $F$ is additive, then its extension commutes with arbitrary direct sums. If $F$ is exact, left exact, or right exact, so is its extension.
56.7 Functors between categories of coherent modules
The following lemma guarantees that we can use the material on functors between categories of quasi-coherent modules when we are given a functor between categories of coherent modules.
Proof. The existence and uniqueness of the extension is a general fact, see Categories, Lemma 4.26.2. To see that the lemma applies observe that coherent modules are of finite presentation (Modules, Lemma 17.12.2) and hence categorically compact objects of $\textit{Mod}(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ by Modules, Lemma 17.22.8. Finally, every quasi-coherent module is a filtered colimit of coherent ones for example by Properties, Lemma 28.22.3.
Assume $F$ is additive. If $\mathcal{F} = \bigoplus _{j \in J} \mathcal{H}_ j$ with $\mathcal{H}_ j$ quasi-coherent, then $\mathcal{F} = \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{J' \subset J\text{ finite}} \bigoplus _{j \in J'} \mathcal{H}_ j$. Denoting the extension of $F$ also by $F$ we obtain
Thus $F$ commutes with arbitrary direct sums.
Suppose $0 \to \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{F}' \to \mathcal{F}'' \to 0$ is a short exact sequence of quasi-coherent $\mathcal{O}_ X$-modules. Then we write $\mathcal{F}' = \bigcup \mathcal{F}'_ i$ as the union of its coherent submodules, see Properties, Lemma 28.22.3. Denote $\mathcal{F}''_ i \subset \mathcal{F}''$ the image of $\mathcal{F}'_ i$ and denote $\mathcal{F}_ i = \mathcal{F} \cap \mathcal{F}'_ i = \mathop{\mathrm{Ker}}(\mathcal{F}'_ i \to \mathcal{F}''_ i)$. Then it is clear that $\mathcal{F} = \bigcup \mathcal{F}_ i$ and $\mathcal{F}'' = \bigcup \mathcal{F}''_ i$ and that we have short exact sequences
Since the extension commutes with filtered colimits we have $F(\mathcal{F}) = \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{i \in I} F(\mathcal{F}_ i)$, $F(\mathcal{F}') = \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{i \in I} F(\mathcal{F}'_ i)$, and $F(\mathcal{F}'') = \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{i \in I} F(\mathcal{F}''_ i)$. Since filtered colimits are exact (Modules, Lemma 17.3.2) we conclude that exactness properties of $F$ are inherited by its extension. $\square$
Lemma 56.7.2. Let $X$ and $Y$ be Noetherian schemes. Let $F : \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X) \to \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$ be an equivalence of categories. Then there is an isomorphism $f : Y \to X$ and an invertible $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module $\mathcal{L}$ such that $F(\mathcal{F}) = f^*\mathcal{F} \otimes \mathcal{L}$.
Proof. By Lemma 56.7.1 we obtain a unique functor $F' : \mathit{QCoh}(\mathcal{O}_ X) \to \mathit{QCoh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$ extending $F$. The same is true for the quasi-inverse of $F$ and by the uniqueness we conclude that $F'$ is an equivalence. By Proposition 56.6.6 we find an isomorphism $f : Y \to X$ and an invertible $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module $\mathcal{L}$ such that $F'(\mathcal{F}) = f^*\mathcal{F} \otimes \mathcal{L}$. Then $f$ and $\mathcal{L}$ work for $F$ as well. $\square$
Remark 56.7.3. In Lemma 56.7.2 if $X$ and $Y$ are defined over a common base ring $R$ and $F$ is $R$-linear, then the isomorphism $f$ will be a morphism of schemes over $R$.
Lemma 56.7.4. Let $f : V \to X$ be a quasi-finite separated morphism of Noetherian schemes. If there exists a coherent $\mathcal{O}_ V$-module $\mathcal{K}$ whose support is $V$ such that $f_*\mathcal{K}$ is coherent and $R^ qf_*\mathcal{K} = 0$, then $f$ is finite.
Proof. By Zariski's main theorem we can find an open immersion $j : V \to Y$ over $X$ with $\pi : Y \to X$ finite, see More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.43.3. Since $\pi $ is affine the functor $\pi _*$ is exact and faithful on the category of coherent $\mathcal{O}_ X$-modules. Hence we see that $j_*\mathcal{K}$ is coherent and that $R^ qj_*\mathcal{K}$ is zero for $q > 0$. In other words, we reduce to the case discussed in the next paragraph.
Assume $f$ is an open immersion. We may replace $X$ by the scheme theoretic closure of $V$. Assume $X \setminus V$ is nonempty to get a contradiction. Choose a generic point $\xi \in X \setminus V$ of an irreducible component of $X \setminus V$. Looking at the situation after base change by $\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(\mathcal{O}_{X, \xi }) \to X$ using flat base change and using Local Cohomology, Lemma 51.8.2 we reduce to the algebra problem discussed in the next paragraph.
Let $(A, \mathfrak m)$ be a Noetherian local ring. Let $M$ be a finite $A$-module whose support is $\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A)$. Then $H^ i_\mathfrak m(M) \not= 0$ for some $i$. This is true by Dualizing Complexes, Lemma 47.11.1 and the fact that $M$ is not zero hence has finite depth. $\square$
The next lemma can be generalized to the case where $k$ is a Noetherian ring and $X$ flat over $k$ (all other assumptions stay the same).
Lemma 56.7.5. Let $k$ be a field. Let $X$, $Y$ be finite type schemes over $k$ with $X$ separated. There is an equivalence of categories between
the category of $k$-linear exact functors $F : \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X) \to \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$, and
the category of coherent $\mathcal{O}_{X \times Y}$-modules $\mathcal{K}$ which are flat over $X$ and have support finite over $Y$
given by sending $\mathcal{K}$ to the restriction of the functor (56.5.1.1) to $\textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X)$.
Proof. Let $\mathcal{K}$ be as in (2). By Lemma 56.5.7 the functor $F$ given by (56.5.1.1) is exact and $k$-linear. Moreover, $F$ sends $\textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ into $\textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$ for example by Cohomology of Schemes, Lemma 30.26.10.
Let us construct the quasi-inverse to the construction. Let $F$ be as in (1). By Lemma 56.7.1 we can extend $F$ to a $k$-linear exact functor on the categories of quasi-coherent modules which commutes with arbitrary direct sums. By Lemma 56.5.7 the extension corresponds to a unique quasi-coherent module $\mathcal{K}$, flat over $X$, such that $R^ q\text{pr}_{2, *}(\text{pr}_1^*\mathcal{F} \otimes _{\mathcal{O}_{X \times Y}} \mathcal{K}) = 0$ for $q > 0$ for all quasi-coherent $\mathcal{O}_ X$-modules $\mathcal{F}$. Since $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ is a coherent $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module, we conclude from Lemma 56.5.11 that $\mathcal{K}$ is coherent.
For a closed point $x \in X$ denote $\mathcal{O}_ x$ the skyscraper sheaf at $x$ with value the residue field of $x$. We have
Since $x \times Y \to Y$ is finite, we see that the pushforward along this morphism is faithful. Hence if $y \in Y$ is in the image of the support of $\mathcal{K}|_{x \times Y}$, then $y$ is in the support of $F(\mathcal{O}_ x)$.
Let $Z \subset X \times Y$ be the scheme theoretic support $Z$ of $\mathcal{K}$, see Morphisms, Definition 29.5.5. We first prove that $Z \to Y$ is quasi-finite, by proving that its fibres over closed points are finite. Namely, if the fibre of $Z \to Y$ over a closed point $y \in Y$ has dimension $> 0$, then we can find infinitely many pairwise distinct closed points $x_1, x_2, \ldots $ in the image of $Z_ y \to X$. Since we have a surjection $\mathcal{O}_ X \to \bigoplus _{i = 1, \ldots , n} \mathcal{O}_{x_ i}$ we obtain a surjection
By what we said above, the point $y$ is in the support of each of the coherent modules $F(\mathcal{O}_{x_ i})$. Since $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ is a coherent module, this will lead to a contradiction because the stalk of $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ at $y$ will be generated by $< n$ elements if $n$ is large enough. Hence $Z \to Y$ is quasi-finite. Since $\text{pr}_{2, *}\mathcal{K}$ is coherent and $R^ q\text{pr}_{2, *}\mathcal{K} = 0$ for $q > 0$ we conclude that $Z \to Y$ is finite by Lemma 56.7.4. $\square$
Lemma 56.7.6. Let $f : X \to Y$ be a finite type separated morphism of schemes. Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a finite type quasi-coherent module on $X$ with support finite over $Y$ and with $\mathcal{L} = f_*\mathcal{F}$ an invertible $\mathcal{O}_ X$-module. Then there exists a section $s : Y \to X$ such that $\mathcal{F} \cong s_*\mathcal{L}$.
Proof. Looking affine locally this translates into the following algebra problem. Let $A \to B$ be a ring map and let $N$ be a $B$-module which is invertible as an $A$-module. Then the annihilator $J$ of $N$ in $B$ has the property that $A \to B/J$ is an isomorphism. We omit the details. $\square$
Lemma 56.7.7. Let $f : X \to Y$ be a finite type separated morphism of schemes with a section $s : Y \to X$. Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a finite type quasi-coherent module on $X$, set theoretically supported on $s(Y)$ with $\mathcal{L} = f_*\mathcal{F}$ an invertible $\mathcal{O}_ X$-module. If $Y$ is reduced, then $\mathcal{F} \cong s_*\mathcal{L}$.
Proof. By Lemma 56.7.6 there exists a section $s' : Y \to X$ such that $\mathcal{F} = s'_*\mathcal{L}$. Since $s'(Y)$ and $s(Y)$ have the same underlying closed subset and since both are reduced closed subschemes of $X$, they have to be equal. Hence $s = s'$ and the lemma holds. $\square$
Lemma 56.7.8. Let $k$ be a field. Let $X$, $Y$ be finite type schemes over $k$ with $X$ separated and $Y$ reduced. If there is a $k$-linear equivalence $F : \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X) \to \textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ Y)$ of categories, then there is an isomorphism $f : Y \to X$ over $k$ and an invertible $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module $\mathcal{L}$ such that $F(\mathcal{F}) = f^*\mathcal{F} \otimes \mathcal{L}$.
Proof using Gabriel-Rosenberg reconstruction. This lemma is a weak form of the results discussed in Lemma 56.7.2 and Remark 56.7.3. $\square$
Proof not relying on Gabriel-Rosenberg reconstruction. By Lemma 56.7.5 we obtain a coherent $\mathcal{O}_{X \times Y}$-module $\mathcal{K}$ which is flat over $X$ with support finite over $Y$ such that $F$ is given by the restriction of the functor (56.5.1.1) to $\textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X)$. If we can show that $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ is an invertible $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module, then by Lemma 56.7.6 we see that $\mathcal{K} = s_*\mathcal{L}$ for some section $s : Y \to X \times Y$ of $\text{pr}_2$ and some invertible $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module $\mathcal{L}$. This will show that $F$ has the form indicated with $f = \text{pr}_1 \circ s$. Some details omitted.
It remains to show that $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ is invertible. We only sketch the proof and we omit some of the details. For a closed point $x \in X$ we denote $\mathcal{O}_ x$ in $\textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ the skyscraper sheaf at $x$ with value $\kappa (x)$. First we observe that the only simple objects of the category $\textit{Coh}(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ are these skyscraper sheaves $\mathcal{O}_ x$. The same is true for $Y$. Hence for every closed point $y \in Y$ there exists a closed point $x \in X$ such that $\mathcal{O}_ y \cong F(\mathcal{O}_ x)$. Moreover, looking at endomorphisms we find that $\kappa (x) \cong \kappa (y)$ as finite extensions of $k$. Then
This implies that the stalk of the coherent $\mathcal{O}_ Y$-module $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ at $y \in Y$ can be generated by $1$ generator (and no less) for each closed point $y \in Y$. It follows immediately that $F(\mathcal{O}_ X)$ is locally generated by $1$ element (and no less) and since $Y$ is reduced this indeed tells us it is an invertible module. $\square$
Post a comment
Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.
In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$
). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).
All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.
Comments (0)