Definition 4.3.1. Given a category $\mathcal{C}$ the opposite category $\mathcal{C}^{opp}$ is the category with the same objects as $\mathcal{C}$ but all morphisms reversed.
4.3 Opposite Categories and the Yoneda Lemma
In other words $\mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\mathcal{C}^{opp}}(x, y) = \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(y, x)$. Composition in $\mathcal{C}^{opp}$ is the same as in $\mathcal{C}$ except backwards: if $\phi : y \to z$ and $\psi : x \to y$ are morphisms in $\mathcal{C}^{opp}$, in other words arrows $z \to y$ and $y \to x$ in $\mathcal{C}$, then $\phi \circ ^{opp} \psi $ is the morphism $x \to z$ of $\mathcal{C}^{opp}$ which corresponds to the composition $z \to y \to x$ in $\mathcal{C}$.
Definition 4.3.2. Let $\mathcal{C}$, $\mathcal{S}$ be categories. A contravariant functor $F$ from $\mathcal{C}$ to $\mathcal{S}$ is a functor $\mathcal{C}^{opp}\to \mathcal{S}$.
Concretely, a contravariant functor $F$ is given by a map $F : \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}) \to \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{S})$ and for every morphism $\psi : x \to y$ in $\mathcal{C}$ a morphism $F(\psi ) : F(y) \to F(x)$. These should satisfy the property that, given another morphism $\phi : y \to z$, we have $F(\phi \circ \psi ) = F(\psi ) \circ F(\phi )$ as morphisms $F(z) \to F(x)$. (Note the reverse of order.)
Definition 4.3.3. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category.
A presheaf of sets on $\mathcal{C}$ or simply a presheaf is a contravariant functor $F$ from $\mathcal{C}$ to $\textit{Sets}$.
The category of presheaves is denoted $\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})$.
Of course the category of presheaves is a proper class.
Example 4.3.4. Functor of points. For any $U\in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ there is a contravariant functor which takes an object $X$ to the set $\mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(X, U)$. In other words $h_ U$ is a presheaf. Given a morphism $f : X\to Y$ the corresponding map $h_ U(f) : \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(Y, U)\to \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(X, U)$ takes $\phi $ to $\phi \circ f$. We will always denote this presheaf $h_ U : \mathcal{C}^{opp} \to \textit{Sets}$. It is called the representable presheaf associated to $U$. If $\mathcal{C}$ is the category of schemes this functor is sometimes referred to as the functor of points of $U$.
Note that given a morphism $\phi : U \to V$ in $\mathcal{C}$ we get a corresponding natural transformation of functors $h(\phi ) : h_ U \to h_ V$ defined by composing with the morphism $U \to V$. This turns composition of morphisms in $\mathcal{C}$ into composition of transformations of functors. In other words we get a functor
Note that the target is a “big” category, see Remark 4.2.2. On the other hand, $h$ is an actual mathematical object (i.e. a set), compare Remark 4.2.11.
Lemma 4.3.5 (Yoneda lemma). Let $U, V \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$. Given any morphism of functors $s : h_ U \to h_ V$ there is a unique morphism $\phi : U \to V$ such that $h(\phi ) = s$. In other words the functor $h$ is fully faithful. More generally, given any contravariant functor $F$ and any object $U$ of $\mathcal{C}$ we have a natural bijection
Proof. For the first statement, just take $\phi = s_ U(\text{id}_ U) \in \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(U, V)$. For the second statement, given $\xi \in F(U)$ define $s$ by $s_ V : h_ U(V) \to F(V)$ by sending the element $f : V \to U$ of $h_ U(V) = \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(V, U)$ to $F(f)(\xi )$. $\square$
Definition 4.3.6. A contravariant functor $F : \mathcal{C}\to \textit{Sets}$ is said to be representable if it is isomorphic to the functor of points $h_ U$ for some object $U$ of $\mathcal{C}$.
Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category and let $F : \mathcal{C}^{opp} \to \textit{Sets}$ be a representable functor. Choose an object $U$ of $\mathcal{C}$ and an isomorphism $s : h_ U \to F$. The Yoneda lemma guarantees that the pair $(U, s)$ is unique up to unique isomorphism. The object $U$ is called an object representing $F$. By the Yoneda lemma the transformation $s$ corresponds to a unique element $\xi \in F(U)$. This element is called the universal object. It has the property that for $V \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ the map
is a bijection. Thus $\xi $ is universal in the sense that every element of $F(V)$ is equal to the image of $\xi $ via $F(f)$ for a unique morphism $f : V \to U$ in $\mathcal{C}$.
Post a comment
Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.
In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$
). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).
All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.
Comments (13)
Comment #1325 by jojo on
Comment #1347 by Johan on
Comment #2149 by Maik Pickl on
Comment #2185 by Johan on
Comment #2377 by Anoop Singh on
Comment #2380 by Johan on
Comment #4960 by Siddharth Bhat on
Comment #5213 by Johan on
Comment #5811 by Zeyn Sahilliogullari on
Comment #5812 by Johan on
Comment #6240 by Yuto Masamura on
Comment #8427 by Elías Guisado on
Comment #9048 by Stacks project on